THE JERSEY VOTING
SYSTEM
David Marrani
This article aims to show the
potential variations that may be brought in the democratic operation in Jersey.
Assuming that any of those variations is in effect a result of both the
political parties and voting systems in place, the changes in Jersey’s
voting system and the development of political parties should have significant
outcomes for the Island. The quality of representative democracy depends mostly on electoral results but also on the level
of political competition and public participation. In turn, party systems and
electoral results are themselves affected by the voting system. The article
seeks to analyse briefly the new constitutional design, and in particular the
possibility offered by the new voting system and the new political competition
in term of efficiency but also of disaffection of the people towards elections
and democracy
1
The emergence in Jersey of a
number of political parties and movements, formed or nearly formed to contest
the elections in June 2022, gives rise to reflections upon the voting system
and the nature of democracy in the
Island.
2
One of the elements of the
theoretical foundation of representative democracy has been the idea that
competitive elections should bring to
power a political elite selected by the people. But nowadays, political
principles such as democracy, nation state, or elections, are no longer in harmony with the current
episteme of our time. Political disengagement,1 political
disenchantment,2 or simply a disdain for elections, are post-modern
symptoms, as put by Professor Maffesoli, of the general lack of affection for the
political.3 It has become quite
1 E Uberoi and N Johnston, “Political Disengagement in
the UK: Who is Engaged?”, House of Commons Briefing Paper, CBP 7501, 25
February 2021.
https://researchbriefings.files.parliament.uk/documents/CBP-7501/CB P-7501.pdf
. Last accessed 22 March 2021.
2 A Bilgrami, “Democracy and Disenchantment”,
(2009) 37(11/12) Social Scientist 4–21.
3 M Maffesoli, Les
Nouveaux Bien-Pensants (Paris: Editions du moment, 2013), esp pp
78–79.
usual for democracies to bring changes to electoral or representative
systems in order to counter those symptoms.
3
With the States of Jersey
approving major reforms to political representation in the Island,4
elections are becoming quite topical. Indeed, with the abolition of senators,
elected on an Island-wide basis, representation seems to be moving towards
new shores.
4
The idea here is not to comment on
or to criticise the change in the number of elected representatives but rather
to take a closer look at the constant
reference to the so-called “modernisation” of Jersey’s voting
system. Although one should probably call it a contemporary move rather than a
modernisation, one should not focus on the representatives or their number but
rather speak or write about the voting system itself.
5
After several reports and debates
relating to elections in Jersey, it may be useful to analyse briefly the
question of voting systems, and then to look at the current and future
situation in Jersey.
Voting systems
6
Elections have always
been an issue in
democracy that triggers both vivid and extensive debates. But
they are peculiar and ambivalent tools.
7
On the one hand, they have not
only been part of the democratic ritual but also have sometimes been a synonym of democracy itself. It is occasionally
argued that elections can be equated with democracy, while at other times they
may solely be considered as one of the variables needed to qualify a government
as democratic. For instance, some scholars adhere to an electoral definition of
democracy where, “Elections, open, free, and fair, are the essence of
democracy, the inescapable sine qua non”.5
Meanwhile, Schumpeter refers to elections
in his seminal work by stating that democracy is a system “for arriving
at political decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by
means of a competitive struggle for the people’s vote”.6
For Sartori, elections are central to democracy as they are a tool for legitimacy. In a democracy, that
legitimacy emanates from the
4 Constitution of the States
and Public Elections (Jersey) Law 2021.
5 S Huntington, The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth
Century (Norman: University of Oklahoma Press, 1991), esp p 9.
6 J Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism
and Democracy (New York: Harper and Row,
1947/1962), esp p 269.
basis that it is the emanation of popular will.7 Elections here
are the guarantee of a democratic functioning society because they permit the
public to select and sanction: a democracy can only survive in the long term if it succeeds as a system of
government.8 It is in fact defined by Sartori as a polyarchy of
elected elites, a system of selection based on the election of competing
minorities.9 What we may
simply explain here is that that “democracy is defined by the
insurmountable boundary that prevents the political subject from becoming
consubstantial with power”.10
8
On the other hand, elections have
not been solely linked to democracy. The pays
d’élections in medieval France, for example, were
administrative units specifically designed to levy taxes. Originally, the agent
in charge was elected, l’élu, later replaced by someone
called élu, but appointed
rather than elected.11 More importantly, kings in the French
monarchy have always been “appointed” following a specific ritual electio, onctio, coronatio (election,
“blessing”, coronation).12 The primary question we
should therefore consider is why do we need to elect anyone?
Why do we need elections in democracy?
9
We have seen that elections are
considered either as the essence of democracy or as a crucial part of it. In a
political system operating on the principle of a representative government, the
primary function of the election is to enable citizens to choose their
representatives and ultimately their leaders, who will oversee designing,
voting and implementing the law on their behalf. Elections are therefore a
delegation of sovereignty to representatives. We must consider in turn the
terminology here: representation, delegation and sovereignty.
Representation
10 What is re-presented,
what is presented again, “[W]e have delegated to hundreds of non-human
lieutenants the task of disciplining, making, and moving other humans or other
non-humans
7 G Sartori, The Theory of Democracy
Revisited (Chatham NJ: Chatham
House Publishers, 1987), esp p 34.
8 Sartori, Theory of Democracy, pp 84–91, esp p 91.
9 Ibid, p 108.
10 C Breger,
“The Leader’s Two Bodies, Slavoj Zizek’s Postmodern Political
Theology” (2001) 31(1) Diacritics 73–90,
esp pp 78–79.
11 J-J Sueur, Histoire du Droit Public Français (Paris; PUF, 2007), esp p 335.
12 D Marrani,
“The Importance of the Symbolic Role of the Head of State”, (2011)
13 European Journal of Law Reform 1,
esp p 44.
. . .”, and therefore we have “instruments [that] bring far
away places, objects and times to us which are thus represented—this is
presented again—for our inspection.”13 Political
institutions appear in front of us.14 Let us not forget that the
dichotomy in law between a natural person and an artificial legal person has
one crucial difference: in the case of a natural person we have a real human;
in the case of a legal person we have a fiction that needs physical agents. In
consequence, one “exists”, the other does not; one is
“alive”, the other is not. Legal persons, including public persons
like corporations or states, need something or someone to give us the feeling
that they are what they are. There is no institution without representation. An
institution creates the presence of a fiction (a legal person) that is
otherwise absent. Representation is the presence of the absent. In that sense,
it gives life to the institution: it institutionalises. We could remember here
Derrida’s thoughts on representation in his comments on Rousseau. He
tells us that the represented signified that “the sovereign people” are represented by
“the assembly”, being therefore the representative signifier.15
The institution will rule for or on behalf of the sovereign; hence the idea of
a delegation of sovereignty. The representation follows a primitive presence
and occurs when the signified is absent. Derrida goes on demonstrating that the
representative is not the represented (the signifier is not the signified), but
is only the representative of the represented (only the signifier, in fact). As
representative, it is not simply the other of the represented. The wrong/bad of
the representative or of the supplement of the presence is neither the same nor
the other. It comes at the moment of the différence,
when the sovereign will is delegated and as a consequence when the Law is
written.16
13 B Latour, “Visualisation and Social Reproduction: Opening
One Eye while Closing the Other . . . a Note on Some Religious
Paintings”, (1987) 35(S1) Sociological
Review, Special Issue (eds G Fyfe and J Law) Picturing Power: Visual Depiction and Social Relations 15–38,
esp p 15.
14 For Heidegger “to appear” is what is in front of
us, what “appears”, as in ancient Greek, “instituted”
always signified what was left in front of us, in other words, what appears. M
Heidegger, Qu’appele-t- on Penser? (Paris:
PUF, 1959), esp p 189.
15 J Derrida, De la Grammatologie (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1994), p 418.
16 Ibid,
p 419.
Delegation
11
Delegation was defined by Thatcher
and Sweet Stone as “an authoritative decision, formalised as a matter of
public law”; the decision:
“transfers policy making authority away from established,
representative organs (those that are directly elected, or are managed directly
by elected politicians), to a non-majoritarian institution, whether public or
private.”17
12
According to Lupia and McCubbins,
“citizens delegate to elected representatives . . . who delegate to
others”.18 Therefore, a parliamentary system of government
imposes a chain linking the “voters” to the ultimate policy-makers.19
This has been clarified by several authors who qualified it as a chain of
delegation.20 Strom, for instance, has identified “four
discrete steps” in this chain of delegation:21
(i) From voters to elected representatives,
(ii)
From legislators to executive
branch, specifically to the head of government (the prime minister),
(iii)
From the head of government (prime
minister) to the heads of different executive departments, and
(iv)
From the head of different executive
departments to civil servants.
13
Delegation is crucial in modern
and contemporary democracies. Indeed, “if delegation makes sense . . .
all other things considered, then no constitutional principle of democracy can justify not
17 M Thatcher and A Stone Sweet, “Theory and Practice of
Delegation to Non-majoritarian Institutions”, in M Thatcher and A Stone
Sweet (eds), The Politics of Delegation (London:
Cass, 2003), p 3.
18 A Lupia and M McCubbins, “Representation or
Abdication? How Citizens use
Institutions to help Delegation Succeed”, (2000) 37(3) European Journal of Political Research 291–307.
19 T Bergman, WC Muller and K Strom, “Introduction:
Parliamentary Democracy and the Chain of Delegation”, (2000) 37(3) European Journal of Political Research 255–260.
20 Ibid,
p 257.
21 K Strom, “Delegation and Accountability in
Parliamentary Democracies”, (2000) 37(3) European Journal of Political Research 261–289, esp p 267.
delegating.”22 It is also instrumental in the link
between elections and democracy, as there is a need to delegate to elected
representatives.
Sovereignty
14
The concept linked to the word
“sovereignty” suggests the idea of supreme power, of ultimate
authority.23 It relates to power that cannot be shared. Sovereignty
refers primarily to a monarch. It can also be attached to an institution
(contained in the idea of the sovereignty of Parliament, for example), or to
some fictional entity (like that of the sovereignty of the nation or the
sovereignty of the people, le public for Rousseau)24 in the
course of the passage from monarchy to democracy.25 In a society
that we assume to be democratic, the role of sovereign moves from the head of
state and becomes attached to an institution, such as parliament, or to a
fictional entity, like “the people”
or “the nation”. As stressed by Laclau and Mouffle,
“democracy inaugurates the experience of a society . . . in which
the people will be proclaimed sovereign, but in which its identity will never
be definitely given, but will remain latent.”26
Perhaps, the sole issue here is that the signifier
“sovereignty” represents different signified concepts: it has one image accoustique that may be used in different
types of political regime. What becomes important, therefore, is the signifier
word “sovereignty” over the signified concept. The core problem between sovereignty and election is the
question of where the sovereignty vested or resided (for instance, in a democracy it could be the people) but also about
who could exercise it: i.e. the people by referendum in a direct democracy
22 DM Kahan, “Democracy Schmemocrac”, (1988–1999) 20 Cardozo L Rev
795–806, esp p 806.
23 See what Troper has to state about the four definitions of
sovereignty in http://www.droitconstitutionnel.net/Souverainete.htm.
Last accessed 22 March 2021.
24 JJ Rousseau, Du Contrat Social
(Paris: Larousse, 1973),
p 30.
25 In the association described by Rousseau, every individual
associates to create a moral person. Rousseau
identified that the republic (named city in the
past), was called state (Etat) when “passive” and sovereign (souverain)
when “active” (ibid, p
30). He developed this idea by explaining that “ le pacte social donne au corps politique un pouvoir absolu sur [tous
ses membres], et c’est ce même pouvoir qui, dirige par la
volonté générale, porte .
. . le nom de souveraineté”
(ibid, p 40).
26 E Laclau and Couffe, Hegemony
and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical
Democratic Politics (London: Verso, 2001), p 187.
or parliament in a representative democracy . . . hence the question of elections.
15
But elections have changed in
nature with the permanent dissatisfaction of the people, and distrust in
political elites. Within an organised society they have become a “safety
valve”. Indeed, the possibility for citizens to be able regularly to express
their dissatisfaction or, conversely, to give a new mandate to the outgoing
power, prevents major political disagreements finding another mode of expression (such as the street) and
other modalities (such as violence). We tend to protest more but, despite our
dissatisfaction, we continue to vote for mainstream parties, alternating
between them.27 The discussion does not take place inside the place
for debates that is parliament (the place where we parle). Parliaments no longer have the absolute power in law making
or even, of representation. Other representatives, as well as more favoured
places of debate, have emerged: journalists, parties, unions, associations,
religious movements, NGOs and, in more contemporary times, social networks, are all representatives and active
transformers of citizens’ aspirations.28
Parliaments no longer have a monopoly of representation
and, according to Shwartzenberg, democracy becomes supplétive rather than representative.29 The
pressure on government seems to be from the “street” (see the
French experience of 1968 and 2005), real or virtual, and not from the members
of Parliament, leaving representation
inefficient. Of course, elections may help to resolve a crisis. Either in an
institutional crisis, like a non- synchronisation between executive and
legislature, or in a deeper debate dividing citizens, an election can help to
find a solution.30 For example, in France during the events of May
1968, the dissolution of the National Assembly and the call for general
elections was used to calm tensions on the street but also to reassure the
traditional strata of the society. Elections may thus be used as a political
strategy to retain (or regain) power.
27 This is either cynical, see Žižek (S
Žižek, The Sublime Object of
Ideology (London, Verso, 2009), or a type of reactionary or obscure
subjectivity, see Badiou (A Badiou, Logics of Worlds, trans. A Toscano
(London: Bloomsbury Academic,
2013).
28 L Sfez, La symbolique politique
(Paris: Que sais je ? PUF,
1996), p 10.
29 P Ardant, Institutions
politiques et Droit constitutionnel (Paris: LGDJ, 2002), p 532.
30 See D Marrani, Dynamics
in the French Constitution, Decoding French Republican Ideas (London:
Routledge, 2013), esp Chapter 1.
General principles
16
It is trivial to state that in an
election what is important is the action
of selecting someone. The meaning of the word “eligere” is simply about choosing someone. For Sartori,
elections are an operation of
selection, not of choice left to chance.31 The idea is that all ballots, voting procedures and
calculation methods are devised in order to separate the candidates. The
general principle of Europe’s electoral heritage, according to the Venice
Commission, is that the vote is (quasi-) universal, with equal free suffrage,
secret, direct and frequent.32 A vote is in fact only ever
quasi-universal because not everyone who has the right to vote in a society has
the right actually to cast a vote.
That said, the citizens, as defined by the state in its constitution, for
example, may all vote. It is universal for these citizens. It is therefore a
complex mater to determine who the citizens are (according to criteria of age,
nationality and residence, for example) but when this is done, the suffrage is
universal.33 The suffrage is equal: equal in rights, equal in voting
powers, equal according to the limit of a constituency or in comparison between
constituencies, equal between males and females. Free suffrage necessitates
citizens being able to form their
own opinions and impact on media coverage, for example, by obliging governments
to enact legislation that will not favour one party (the ruling one for
instance) but contribute to pluralism. This helps to prevent distorted results.
But free suffrage is also concerned with how a voter can freely express his wish and how his ballot will
be counted. Secrecy of suffrage is important to allow the vote to be as free as
possible, and has to be direct, that is, that a citizen must be able to vote
directly for a candidate, although sometimes there could be a little indirect
mediation. The frequency of elections is also a principle. Frequent elections
allow the people to be consulted often.
Different types of electoral systems
17
The ballot may be first past the
post (voting for one candidate) or a
list (voting for a list of candidates), a majority in one or two rounds,
proportional or mixed (a mixture of majority and proportional elections). The choice of electoral systems
is linked to local or
31 Sartori, Theory of Democracy, esp p 85.
32 https://www.venice.coe.int/webforms/documents/?pdf=CDL-STD(2013)05
0-e. Last accessed
22 March 2021.
33 See D Marrani,
Dynamics of the French
Constitution, chapter on New
Caledonia.
national political
history, but needs pluralism, the opinion of the parties.
18
The term suffrage refers to the act of voting by which one declares
one’s policy choices, but it also expresses the right to vote.
19 Thus, the vote can be:
(i)
restricted, if it is limited to a
class of people based on their income (poll tax), or the level of their
knowledge (capability suffrage);
(ii) universal, if all adult citizens
vote;
(iii) live, if the voter
votes for himself as a candidate;
(iv)
indirect, if the candidate is
elected by an electoral college appointed directly by the citizens.
20
Electoral systems denote a set of
characteristics involving voting methods, allocation of seats in the
assemblies, and the essential elements of a plan (number of parties, government
stability or instability). The choice of an electoral system, particularly the
voting system, reflects political goals. Thus, it is generally considered that the system of proportional representation
allows a consistent representation of citizens to vote, but may pose a
risk of governmental
instability. A majority vote generally avoids such instability.
Different types of electoral systems
and their effects
21
Casting a vote brings the wish of
one individual member of society into
the public sphere. At the same time, it contributes to the formation of a
majority, even a governing majority. It will then be instrumental in the
appointment of elected officials. The electoral system covers all the elements
of the election and its consequences (effects on the organisation of parties,
for example, etc).
22
One of the most important
principles is universal suffrage. That principle is nowadays omnipresent in
representative democracies. That is
not the case, for electoral systems vary in accordance with considerations such
as national or local political history, needs for representation, pluralism,
and so on. Voting procedures may also vary.
France has experienced significant changes since 1871, for instance, in how a vote may be cast in general elections,
while the UK has had a similar system since the eighteenth century.
The classification of electoral systems
23 According to Pippa Norris, there are four main types of
electoral systems: majoritarian, proportional, semi-proportional and mixed.34
24
The oldest voting system is the
majoritarian, which is used by 83 countries. It is based on the allocation of
one (single-member constituencies) or more (multi-member ballot) seats to the
person or persons obtaining the most votes on election day. It may be a plurality or first past the post system, or a second ballot
majority of two rounds.
25
In plurality elections or first
past the post, sometimes known as a plurality single-member district system,
the candidate who gets the most votes wins the seat (e.g. UK general elections for the House of Commons). The winner is
therefore the candidate with the most votes but not necessarily with
an absolute majority of the votes. This has
the advantage of simplicity. However, it often leads to over representation of
the leading party or parties and under-representation of the others. There is
normally no need for an absolute majority. What counts is therefore the share of national representation rather the share of voters. It could
be the case that some parties get almost no
elected candidates. Moreover, the geographical representation of parties
greatly influences the final result to the extent that a small,
well-established party can be overrepresented, but also a party with the most votes at the national level may
be deprived of victory because its
votes are spread too thinly.
26
When this system is used in
multi-member districts, it becomes a block vote where voters have as many votes
as there are seats to be filled. Here, the highest-polling candidates fill the
positions regardless of the percentage of the votes they achieve. It has an
impact on other aspects of the political life. Indeed, party lists should be
presented instead of individual candidates (and we can end up in a party block vote).
27
In the first past two rounds (eg in France) or second ballot majority,
success in the first round is determined by obtaining an absolute majority of
votes, sometimes with the obligation of having a minimum number of registered
voters. Having failed to reach this threshold, a second round is held. Access
to the second round is regulated: the two leading candidates in the first round (French
34 P Norris, “Choosing Electoral Systems: Proportional,
Majoritarian and Mixed Systems”, (1997) 18(3) Contrasting Political Institutions 297–312, Special Issue
(eds J Laponce and B Saint-Jacques) esp p 299. Discussions on the electoral
systems will mostly use this article.
presidential election); a minimum number of votes or percentage of
registered electors (French legislative elections for the National Assembly).
Compared to the single ballot system, the ability to form alliances for the
second round smooths distortions: small parties can get along with larger ones
to get their voices heard, in exchange for a deferral voice elsewhere. In
contrast, those who do not subscribe to an alliance are often deprived of
representation.
28
In alternative vote systems,
candidates are ranked by the electors (1, 2, 3 etc) and win if they obtain an absolute majority; otherwise the
last candidate is eliminated and his or her votes redistributed until an
absolute majority is reached (Ireland, presidential elections, and Australia,
House of Representative elections).
Proportional electoral system
29 The proportional system is used in 57 countries. It is simple in
principle—seats are allocated according to the number of votes—but
complicated in its implementation. It grew with the role of political parties
“in between” the people and the political elites: it is less a vote
for an individual than for a party or programme.
30
Several methods exist to split
votes. The number of votes needed to
win a seat is decided through a specific formula. The number of seats allocated
to each list is then defined by dividing the total number of votes obtained by
each list by an electoral quotient deriving from the formula used. After the
first allocation is completed, the remaining seats are distributed either according to the largest
remainder formula that favours small parties or the highest average formula
that favours large ones. In the first method, a minimum quota is used which can be calculated in several ways: with the
Hare quota, the total number of valid votes in each constituency is divided by
the total number of seats to be allocated (Denmark and Costa Rica); the Droop
quota raises the divisor by the number of seats plus one (South Africa and
Greece). In the alternative method, seats are then allocated to parties that
secure the highest resulting quotient, up to the total number of seats
available according to the d’Hondt formula, using divisors (such as 1, 2,
3 etc), the “pure”
Saint-Laguë method divides the votes with odd numbers (1, 3, 5, 7 etc) and the “modified”
Saint- Laguë replaces the first divisor by 1.4 but is otherwise identical
to the pure version.
31
There are other methods of
distribution, such as the clearing systems used in Germany. The seats are
divided from the list by order of most frequent, but sometimes depending on the
indication of preferences given by the voters.
32
In proportional systems, the
threshold for the right to the distribution of seats and the size of the
constituency are key variables. The higher the threshold, the greater the
number of major constituencies and the more difficulty small parties have
gaining seats. Some countries (eg, Israel) choose to have only one constituency in the country. The threshold
level depends on the characteristics of each country. Set at 5% in Germany or
France, it does not affect major national parties but in young democracies,
with a large number of parties, it
could deprive a large segment of the population of representation.
The semi-proportional system
33 There are a few semi-proportional systems, such as the cumulative
vote, the limited vote, or the single transferable vote. In the cumulative vote, electors are given as
many votes as representatives, and votes can be accumulated on a single
candidate. In the limited vote, electors are given fewer votes than the number
of representatives. The single
transferable vote, currently employed in legislative elections in Ireland, is
explained by Norris—
“a country is divided into multi-member constituencies which each
have about four or five representatives. Parties put forward as many candidates
as they think could win in each constituency. Voters rank their preferences
among candidates (1, 2, 3, 4 . . .). The total number of votes is counted, and
then the number of seats divides this total in the constituency to produce a
quota. To be elected, candidates must reach the minimum quota. When the first
preferences are counted, if no candidates reach the quota, then the person with
the least votes is eliminated, and their votes redistributed according to
second preferences. This process continues until all seats are filled.”35
Mixed systems
34
Finally, the mixed systems borrow
elements from the majoritarian and proportional systems. They combine, but with
great diversity, both mechanisms,
aiming to combine the advantages and to minimize the disadvantages of both
methods.
35
For example, the voting system
used in France for municipal elections in towns of more than 1,000 inhabitants
aims to ensure a majority for the winner, allowing alliances between rounds and
giving representation to the minority. Thus,
after the second
round, the
35 Norris, p 301.
winner gets half of the seats,
and the other half is distributed
proportionally among those parties with at least 5% of the vote.
36
After considering elections through
the abstract lens of voting systems, it is time to examine what
the situation in Jersey.
Current and future situation in Jersey
37 According to the States of Jersey Law 2005, art. 2, the
legislature comprised (before the recent amendments) the following members:
“2 Constitution of the States
(1) The States of Jersey are constituted as follows— the
Bailiff;
the Lieutenant-Governor;
8 Senators, elected
as provided by this Law;
the
Connétables of the 12 Parishes of Jersey, who are members of the States
by virtue of their office;
29 Deputies,
elected as provided
by this Law; the Dean of Jersey;
the Attorney
General; the Solicitor General.”
38
Most of its members were therefore
elected, either directly (eight Senators and 29 Deputies) or indirectly (12 Connétables). This changed
following the adoption by the States Assembly of what is now the Constitution of the States and Public Elections (Jersey)
Law 2021. The position is now that the States is an assembly of 49 members,
without senators. 36 Nothing much has been said about the voting system.
36 As explained in the report lodged with the draft
Constitution of the States and Public Elections (Jersey) Law 202-,
“In
December 2020, the Assembly adopted P.139/2020 ‘Composition and Election
of the States: proposed changes’ and .
. . agreed proposals which
will allow progress to finally be made in the delivery of a fairer, better,
simpler, more inviting elections for candidate and voter alike. These
legislative changes implement paragraph (a) of P.139/2020, namely to establish an Assembly of 49 Members,
37 elected from 9 new districts of comparable population
size, plus the 12 Parish Conn- étables.”
39 According to Dr Renwick—
“Jersey currently uses plurality voting in all three parts of the
electoral system. Connétables are
elected using single-member plurality (commonly, though misleadingly, known as
‘first past the post’), as are the Deputies in the parishes and
districts that elect one Deputy. Multimember plurality (commonly, but again
misleadingly, known as the ‘block vote’ system) is used to elect
the Deputies in multi-member parishes and districts as well as the ten Senators.”37
40
The introduction of the new super
constituencies, nine districts with three to five deputies, will influence the
voting system in Jersey. It would see an exacerbation of the block votes
system, a sort of offshoot of the first past the post for multi-member
districts. The use of plurality
voting in the new nine multi-member districts will mean that voters will have
as many votes as there are seats to
be filled in the district. Although it is not clarified, it is often the case
that voters are left free to vote for candidates regardless of any party
affiliation.
41
We may foresee quite a lot of
issues here. The first issue will be that voters will vote for individual
candidates within their reasonably sized geographical districts. The second,
though related to the first, is that it might have the effect of increasing the
need for and the role of political parties if we compare this system with first
past the post. In addition, as a third issue, we may see unpredictable and
sometimes undesirable impacts on election results. For instance, voters may
cast all their votes for the candidates of a single party, pushing the most
disastrous disadvantage of the first past the post system of
disproportionality. This might effect a serious distortion of a parliamentary
system such as that of Jersey.38 The fourth issue is that voters may
be able to vote for more than one party in the same district, triggering an actual competition within the members
of the
https://statesassembly.gov.je/assemblypropositions/2021/p.17-2021.pdf.
Last accessed 22 March 2021.
37 A Renwick, ‘The Jersey States Assembly in Comparative
Perspective’, A Report for the States of Jersey Electoral Commission
(2012), esp p 15. https:
//statesassembly.gov.je/sitecollectiondocuments/states%20assembly/the%20je
rsey%20states%20assembly%20in%20comparative%20perspective,%20dr.% 20alan%20renwick,%20university%20of%20reading.pdf.
Last accessed 22 March 2021.
38 It might be said that that fear was realised in the recent
elections in Sark— having the number of votes match the number of
candidates to be elected means that the “list” with minority
support is wiped out.
same party who would then be in competition with each other. That may
contribute to factions and eventually to corruption.39 One may want
to look at the Guernsey 2020 election results which seem to demonstrate that
candidates forming themselves into parties does not guarantee that voters will
practise party politics.40
42
We should distinguish the block
vote and the party block vote. The
difference between the two is that in a party block vote, voters choose between
party lists of candidates rather than individuals. A block vote is therefore
more common in countries with weak or non- existent political parties. In a
party block vote, seats in a district are given to the party with a plurality
of the total vote. The main advantage
is to allow for the representation of balanced minorities, often ethnic, by
giving parties the opportunity to have diversity in the lists of candidates.41
As we know from Renwick—
39 As explained by Norris, most voting systems have advantages
and disadvantages. Debates about
voting systems are often due to the
difficulty of reconciling
several goals and political objectives. For people advocating the proportional
system, an electoral system must
give a true and fair view of the
political situation and the electorate; for people advocating the majoritarian system,
the aim is to achieve a majority of elected officials who can govern. There are
mechanisms involved in another battle,
that is, between
two visions of democracy, one
based on the representation of the people and the other on the efficiency of
government. Beyond the simple allocation of seats, the choice of voting system
is the reflection of a conception of political life. Proportional systems often
lead to dysfunction of the political system; they favour a multiparty system
and give an important role to small parties, which often become indispensable
partners for majorities to exist (as in the Fourth Republic in France or in
Italy). Majority voting in elections favour alternating,
but only between two parties (the United Kingdom, for example).
The majority vote in two rounds; that of the Fifth Republic has the flexibility
of alternating and encourages more parties to form alliances for the second
round. Proportional systems complicate the emergence of a stable and coherent
majority, giving precedence to a logic of cooperation of the parties (parties share power as seats). Conversely, majority voting most often leads to
the appearance of stable majorities based on a confrontation with the
opposition (the coalition that wins governs) but at the cost of injustice in representation.
40 The Results of the 2020 General Election—Election 2020
Guernsey. https://election2020.gg/. [Last accessed 3 September 2021.]
41 K Lundell, Contextual
Determinants of Electoral System Choice, A Macro Comparative Study
1945–2003 (Åbo, Finland: Åbo Akademi University Press,
2005), esp p 33.
“Politics in Jersey being non-partisan, list-based systems—
closed-, flexible-, or open-list proportional systems, mixed- parallel or
mixed-compensatory systems, or bonus-adjusted systems—would be
incongruous. Though some in Jersey may advocate the development of a party
system, it would be quite inappropriate to seek to force that precipitately
through the design of the electoral
system.”42
43
As of today, Jersey’s
political party numbers are increasing. Reform Jersey, a party that holds five seats at the States, is now joined
by the Progress Party, created at the beginning of 2021, with two seats. More
recently, the Alliance Party, with at least five seats, has been registered. It
may be the case that even though the new voting
system does not look like a party block vote, it has already triggered a shift
towards a political pluralism, a characteristic of party block vote.
Conclusion
44 An analogy between Jersey and Monaco may be drawn. As mentioned
by Professor Joël-Benoît d’Onorio, the political system of
Monaco is a system “associant une
monarchie active à une démocratie
effective”.43 If Monaco is perhaps a “more
active” monarchy than Jersey, the democratic aspects of both the
principality and the crown dependency could be compared to illustrate this
short article.
45
Even though, we witness everywhere
“the tremendous lack of interest for . . . elections amongst
ordinary people”, voting
systems are often an important simple set of tools that encourage a competitive recruitment or selection of
political elites.44 They should be taken seriously, as an essential
component of the constitutional engineering of a society. The reform introduced
to the Conseil National, Monaco’s parliament in the 2000s, brought a new voting system
and
42 Renwick, The Jersey States Assembly in Comparative
Perspective, esp p 17.
43 J-B d’Onorio, Monaco, Monarchie
et Démocratie (Aix-Marseille: PU d’Aix-Marseille, 2014.
44 “Michel Maffesoli’s Views on the Recent French Municipal Elections,” https://fede.education/michel-maffesoli-directeur-de-lecole-perigueux-busine
ss-school/?utm_source=rss&utm_medium=rss&utm_campaign=michel-maffe soli-directeur-de-lecole-perigueux-business-school&lang=en. Last accessed
22 March 2021.
the development of a corpus of
competing political parties. What may be expected in 2022 in Jersey is very
similar.
Professor David Marrani, Ph.D, is
the former Dean at the Institute of Law in Jersey and former Senior Lecturer at
the University of Essex, UK. He is currently the Director of the International
Centre of Law and Business and the Avant Garde Interdisciplinary Research
Group. The author would like to thank Giulia-Clara Marrani for her help.